Is critique secular? It’s clear that Talal Asad and Saba Mahmood took this question seriously when preparing these essays; and despite Mahmood’s tacked on last paragraph, the answer is a conclusive No! I’d be interested to hear what they had to say if they moved beyond this question, on to ask, for instance, should critique be secular? Or, how could critique be more secular? Their complication of the secular does more to expose the hypocrisy of interfaith dialogues and ecumenicism (liberal constructions) more generally than to suggest any means beyond, and becomes, unfortunately, another standard critique of empire, with the terms secular, religious, blasphemy, free speech, thrown in.
This book is critical, but is it critique? In a book that seeks to trouble binaries, it’s ironic that the driving logic of each essay is the revelation that there are two wrong systems at work. There’s no monolithic Islam…Okay. But, now there’s a monolithic West. For Asad, the West (and the secular!) is exemplified (as Imre pointed out to me yesterday) by neocons like Fukuyama, and by just plain old cons like Pope Benedict. And for Mahmood, the West is a juridical monoculture. To do a little generalizing myself, I’d say this ironic outcome is due to the elemental confusion within the particularly American school of ideology critique that thinks exposing ideology as such is somehow a moral achievement. In this version of critique two wrongs somehow make a right.
On his first page, Asad exemplifies the category error (or, metalepsis) that acts as a guiding principle: however one figures these vaguely defined antagonisms (between West/East, freedom/fundamentalism, secular/religious, Islam/Europe), it’s assuming too much to claim the debate over the cartoons within the “wider discourse [of] the West’s ‘War on Terror’ ” (20). Isn’t that “War” itself part of a wider discourse that this volume is trying to name? (And if this isn’t Asad’s claim, then he should watch his passive-voice generalizations: “the affair was discussed”; “the cartoon scandal was linked”, “it was argued” (20) etc.). Unmasking the onto-theology at work in liberal states isn’t even really necessary when both neocons and neoliberals (is there a difference?) have publicly and ridiculously appealed to and enlisted religion in their crusade for global democracy, from Ann Coulter’s loudly-touted imperative to Christianize the Middle East, to CNN’s thinktank darling Ayaan Hirsi Ali’s mission to ask for Rome’s help in converting “the immigrant Muslim fifth-column in Europe” (See her recent autobiography, or, last week’s TLS).
However, to be positive for a moment, the topics addressed by Is Critique… are fascinating and rich. And I really enjoyed Asad’s brilliant allegory for the story of Christianity/Democracy (22-3), at least, until it was undone with the analysis of Jesus via free speech (34). It’s true and troubling that democracy at once claims to belong to Christianity (or more often to the pseudo-category “judeo-christian”, which pretends to be inclusive, to subordinate the minority to the majority through both its syntax and its pretence to be historical—but does it actually mean anything?) at the same time as it claims to be secular. But then Zizek does a fine(r) job of reminding us of Christianity’s historical hostility to democracy (First as Tragedy…). And this book at least hints at questions well worth asking. As Asad and Mahmood briefly bring up, it is productive to think this conflict in terms of integration, but what about imagining something worth integrating into? How can Asad’s discussion of the Lockean idea of identity being related to property (28) be fleshed out regarding real property, access to and ownership of material wealth? And would different property relations change anything for the subject of rights that Mahmood defines? But for the most part we’re reminded of things like how free speech is not freedom and is in fact a limitation (32).
My main concern is, as always, how this indictment of abstract equivalent values (which is not at all, as Asad argues, a characteristic of the nation state as such, but rather of its strange bedfellow capital) and its supposedly-attendant elimination of difference (24) implicitly posits difference as such as a virtue. And inevitably, by linking this equivalence to Western politics via alienation (24), the “other” becomes a figure for counterhegemonic or revolutionary resistance. Two wrongs don’t make a right, especially if you’re not even willing to call one of the wrongs a wrong, but insist that it is right(er) by default. Even in Mahmood’s intriguing critique of the juridical there are two wrongs: films offensive to Christians were banned under the same article as Turkey banned books offensive to its majority Muslim population.
Mahmood’s explanation of “Muslim piety” as a mode of perception unfathomable to Western minds is, also, not all that “other”. The sign/image of Mohammed is immediately tied to life; it marks a real relation rather than an arbitrary linguistic connection (76). But isn’t this similar (and perhaps even assimilable) to the Lacanian ideal ego, the image you assume? And then Mohammed or God becomes the ego ideal, the identity you assume to be watching you as you perform your ego ideal? Unfortunately, returning at the end of the essay to this very interesting description of the different modes of perception and relation to the divine in Christianity and Islam, we hear: “I read [the problem] not as an epistemological problem but in terms of the differential of power characteristic of minority-majority relations within the context of nation states” (89). That’s too bad, because it’s actually quite fascinating as an epistemological problem and (laudable, but) unnecessary as a critique of the nation state. This critique of the law as a site to achieve rights (because really this discussion is at bottom about who constitutes a subject of rights, and how such a subject is constituted and who gets left out. That’s always the at least implicit point of the ideology critique which takes as its mission the uncovering of inequality and hypocrisy) comes to a familiar conclusion: it’s biased in favour of the (religious) majority. Maybe a suggestion or two on how to further secularize legal apparatuses would spice things up! But in the end we get the feeling that Mahmood is as exhausted arguing with liberal democratic hegemony as some of us are hearing about it: “I am not sure if either the Muslim immigrant community or the European majority is prepared for such an undertaking” (89)
This American ideology critique that I’m critiquing here is necessarily limited and appears naïve because it wants to pursue the Marxist project without going over to Marxism. Why, for instance do none of our authors cite Marx’s “On the Jewish Question”? In fact, in her new book, Wendy Brown has a chapter called “The Jewish Question and the Woman Question”, yet Marx’s name comes up only twice in the whole book (Bauer gets only one reference!). This Marxophobia leads to an utterly facile moralization that’s not much worse than the uncritical “Us vs. Them”. So there is no us or them, and they are more like us than we think and less like us than we think in other ways, and we are much less like us than we like to think, so this way of thinking is wrong, and we should be more careful, and god forbid we should ask critical questions of a situation in which people died over tasteless cartoons because many of those questions will be asked by the usual gang of idiots and will lead to much similarly tasteless “public debate”. I’m always up for criticizing Christianity and liberalism and onto-theology, but if I were to write about it, I’d want to imagine ways of moving closer to something better than exposing wrongs; for example, let’s push this not-unfamiliar problem of the subject of rights and the place of institutions within its figuration. The essays we looked at this month clearly show that exposing two wrongs does little toward figuring a philosophy of Right.
At the risk of monolithicizing these two essays, two wrongs may prove that I’m right (or at least a third wrong): Asad thinks that the problem is that individuals are made into abstract averages—one vote is equal to any other (24). Mahmood warns religious minorities facing moral injury that majority attitudes are worth more than others (88). Maybe we can find in this contradiction a key to moving not just beyond Western religious bias, but perhaps even further.